A New Hypothesis on Compositionality

نویسندگان

  • Reinhard Blutner
  • Petra Hendriks
چکیده

In this paper we put forward a new hypothesis on compositionality of meaning, namely that compositionality is bidirectional optimization. Underspecification approaches to natural language interpretation generally start with an underspecified or weak meaning, which is strengthened by contextual information. In contrast, the bidirectional optimization approach we advocate proceeds from the strongest possible meaning. This meaning can be changed or weakened by contextual information. Under this approach, the meaning of an utterance is composed in a functional rather than a concatenative way. Hence, this approach avoids a number of well-known empirical problems associated with concatenative compositionality. Styles of Compositionality Van Gelder (1990) distinguishes between concatenative and functional compositionality. He describes the essence of a concatenative mode of combination informally as “a way of linking or ordering successive constituents without altering them in any way as it forms the compound expression.” For example, tokens of the symbol “P” are the same whether appearing standing alone, P, or in the context of an expression such as (P&Q;). Obviously, the thesis of context independency is based on this type of compositionality (cf. Hintikka, 1983, cited in Janssen, 1997): “The meaning of an expression should not depend on the context in which it occurs.” Yet, although formal languages of mathematics, logic, and computer science are all compositional in this concatenative sense, concatenation is not the only way of implementing the combination of elements in getting a compound expression. Van Gelder (1990) points out that functional compositionality can be obtained whenever there are general, effective, and reliable processes for (a) producing an expression given its constituents, and (b) decomposing the expression back into those constituents. Whereas concatenative schemes are always functionally compositional as well, it is possible to have merely functionally compositional schemes that are not concatenative. One useful example for a coding scheme that is merely functionally compositional is the Gödel numbering schema for a formal language. A crucial feature of this scheme is that it is completely reversible. In addition, using the prime decomposition scheme it is possible to calculate the Gödel numbers of the (primitive) constituents of the expression under discussion (cf. van Gelder, 1990, p. 362). One of the key principles in formal approaches to natural language interpretation is the principle of compositionality, which expresses the idea that the meaning of a complex expression can be derived from the meanings of its parts and the way these parts are syntactically linked. Smolensky (1996) notes that “It would constitute significant progress to be able to reduce the (symbolic) principle of semantic compositionality to more basic connectionist principles (...). Developing such a connectionist semantics might well involve formalizing the weak notion of compositionality.” With weak compositionality Smolensky refers to compositionality in an “approximate” sense: a non-concatenative way of combining contextually dependent (representations of) elements of a compound expression. In that sense, Smolensky’s weak compositionality is reminiscent to Frege’s (1884) contextuality principle, cited in Janssen (1997): “A word has a meaning only in the context of a sentence, not in separation.” Compositionality and the Role of Context Notoriously, there are a number of empirical problems with the semantic principle of compositionality. For example, compare the sentence Most people sleep at night to the sentence Most people drink at night. Although the syntactic structures of these two sentences are absolutely identical, the preferred (default) interpretations differ truth-conditionally. The preferred reading of the first sentence can be paraphrased as “At night, most people sleep” whereas the preferred reading of the second sentence is not “At night, most people drink” but rather, “Most people who drink (alcohol), drink at night”. Because these sentences have the same subject, namely most people, at first sight they appear to express conflicting assertions about what most people do. However, they can be simultaneously true in a certain situation for a certain set of people, even if noone of this set of people drinks and sleeps at the same time. In a situation when half of the people drink (they are drinkers) and 80% of these drinkers only drinks at night, the sentence Most people drink at night will be judged true. In the same situation, the sentence Most people sleep at night can be true as well, namely if the people who don’t drink at night (that is, the nondrinkers as well as the day-drinkers), sleep. These two sentences can be true in the same situation because they have different preferred readings. The above two sentences were presented out of context. Because the sentences were presented in written form, no clues were provided with respect to their intonational structure. In addition, their syntactic structures are completely identical. Nevertheless, different preferred readings arise for these sentences. We conclude that in the absence of further context, intonational clues and syntactic differences, these different preferred readings arise as the result of the differences in lexical content in relation to our world knowledge. Although these different readings actually involve different truth conditions, there is no structurally based, mechanical way in which the correct interpretations can be derived. Therefore, sentences like the two above are considered a problem for the principle of compositionality. The above two sentences are quantificational in nature: they contain a quantificational determiner, in this case most. Quantificational determiners are known to establish a relation between two sets. The first set, the domain of quantification, is generally expressed by the noun (together with possible modifiers of the noun) with which the determiner forms a syntactic constituent. However, it can be argued that context always restricts this domain of quantification. Hence, in order to calculate the truth conditions of a quantificational expression, one always has to take into account the context. The truth conditions of a sentence such as Most people drink depend already on what subset of people counts as the domain of quantification of most. Usually, a sentence like this will not be about people in general but rather about some relevant subset of people determined by the context. Obviously, a sentence such as Most of them drink will have varying truth conditions depending on what them refers to. And if the sentence Most drink is uttered out of the blue, the hearer even totally depends on the context in order to determine the relevant set of individuals for the quantifier to live on. At this point, consider the sentence Most drink AT NIGHT. Here, the capitals indicate the accented part of the sentence. If we want to derive the interpretation of this example sentence compositionally, we must assume the presence of an empty noun. The content of this empty structure denotes the whole domain of individuals and gets intersected with a context set variable (cf. Westerståhl, 1985). But in fact, we need two context set variables then. One would be equated with the generalized union over the set of alternatives for the syntactic argument that contains the sentential accent, or focus (cf. de Hoop & Solà, 1996), so that the quantificational domain would be the set of individuals who drink at certain times. The other one would be equated with some additional context set, for example, the set of linguists in Sydney. Hence, in this case we get as the domain of quantification the set of drinking linguists in Sydney. But how many contextual restrictions can or should we add before we may calculate the truth conditions of a quantificational sentence? The question arises when, how and to what extent hearers use different guiding principles to arrive at the proper interpretation of a quantified expression in a given context. As we have seen, different readings do in fact involve different truth conditions. Therefore, we may say that the problem for compositionality just pointed out is a major problem for linguistic theory. Compositionality and Optimization The problem of compositionality, as we pointed it out in the above discussion, is stated by Dekker and van Rooy (2000) as follows: “(...) we cannot systematically determine the semantic content of a sentence in a compositional way based on its syntactic structure, without making reference to the attitudes of speakers and hearers, if we equate the semantic content of a sentence with its truth-conditions (...). So what should we do? Give up compositionality, or give up the assumption that what should be determined compositionally are the truth-conditions of a sentence?” In fact, we will argue that neither of these assumptions has to be given up if we take a broader view on compositionality (van Gelder’s 1990 functional compositionality) in addition to Blutner’s bidirectional optimization view on the relation between form and meaning. But before we explore this hypothesis, let us examine the question what is the current view on compositionality within Optimality Theory. Optimality Theory was developed in the 1990s by Alan Prince and Paul Smolensky as a general theory of language and grammar (cf. Prince & Smolensky, 1993, 1997). Optimality Theory applied to the domains of syntax and semantics involves two closely related issues: 1. given a semantic input, what is its optimal expression?, and 2. given a syntactic input, what is its optimal interpretation? In OT semantics, developed by Hendriks and de Hoop (1997, 2001), each grammatical expression is associated with an, in principle, infinite number of interpretations. These candidate interpretations are tested against a set of ranked constraints in a parallel fashion. One of the advantages of such an approach is that constraints of various nature (syntactic, pragmatic, etc.) interact with each other in a truly cross-modular way. This view crucially differs from the classical compositional approach, where interpretation is computed on the basis of the syntactic input, making use of context only when necessary. Whereas OT syntax optimizes syntactic structure with respect to a semantic input (the so-called speaker’s perspective), OT semantics optimizes interpretation with respect to a syntactic input (the hearer’s perspective). Blutner (2000) extensively argues in favour of bidirectional optimization, where speaker’s and hearer’s optimization are carried out simultaneously. In Blutner’s version of bidirectional OT, a form-meaning pair is called super-optimal if and only if there is no other super-optimal pair such that » (» is an ordering relation which can be read as ‘being more harmonic, being more economical’) and there is no other super-optimal pair such that » . Under the assumption that the relation » is transitive and well-founded, Jäger (2000) proved the above to be a sound recursive definition. With respect to the relation between compositionality and optimization, Zeevat (2000) discusses two relevant constraints, one that prohibits adding material to the content or context of utterance and one that requires us to interpret all that the speaker has said. Satisfaction of these two constraints means interpreting all and only the material available in the utterance and so, their combination “restores important aspects of compositional semantics (not the full principle, but essential aspects)” (Zeevat, 2000). Additionally, in OT syntax, a principle called recoverability relates to compositionality, the idea being that the semantic content of elements that are not pronounced must be recoverable from local context (Pesetsky, 1998; Buchwald et al., 2002; Kennedy, 2002; Vogel, to appear). Kuhn (2001) shows that recoverability effects automatically follow in a (weak) bidirectional optimization model, as in such a system we not only have to check whether a reduced string is the optimal way of expressing the underlying content, we also have to check whether the underlying content is the optimal interpretation of the reduced string. Compositionality and Bidirectionality In Optimality Theory the procedure that provides us with an optimal interpretation of a given form within a certain context can be viewed in two different ways. The first approach combines the view of radical underspecification with a mechanism of contextual enrichment. This approach is taken, for example, in Blutner (1998, 2000). The second approach takes the opposite position in crucial respects. Rather than strengthening a weak (underspecified) meaning with contextual knowledge, we may take as our point of departure the strongest possible meaning and have it weakened by contextual information. This is the approach advocated in Zwarts (2003), who uses an OT approach to interpretation that incorporates the Strongest Meaning Hypothesis of Dalrymple et al. (1994). In the following we adopt the second position without excluding that also the first position may be appropriate under certain conditions. Under the second approach, again syntactic structure, lexical material, context and world knowledge may all help in arriving at the correct interpretation of sentences such as Most people drink at night. But crucially, these different factors do not just function one after the other as reducers of the presumably infinite set of interpretations given by a highly underspecified representation. In fact, the different factors can be in conflict. For example, the lexical meaning of most gives us the relation between two sets such that the intersection contains more elements than the difference between the two does. The lexical material within the sentence and the syntactic structure of the sentence give us these two sets, in this case, the set of people and the set of individuals that drink at night. This would give us the optimal (hence, preferred) interpretation in the absence of further context, and in fact, that would give us the optimal interpretation in the case of Most people sleep at night. For the sentence Most people drink at night, however, this interpretation gives rise to a conflict with our world knowledge. As it is probably not even true that most people drink (where drink is generally understood as drink alcohol), it is hard to believe that it holds for most people that they drink at night. So, there is a conflict between the information provided by the syntactic structure of the sentence and the information provided by our world knowledge. This conflict is resolved by considering the next optimal interpretation (that is, “next optimal” purely on the basis of the syntactic structure of the sentence). This is the interpretation such that the set of people gets intersected with the generalized union over the set of alternatives for a certain constituent in the sentence. If intonational information is available, then the constituent that gives rise to this set of alternatives is the syntactic argument containing the focus (where focus is marked by sentential accent). In the absence of intonation, we may consider what would be the unmarked constituent to bear the focus . In the case of Most people drink at night, the default position of the sentential accent seems to be on at night. This gives us as a domain of quantification of most the set of people who drink (at certain times). Hence, the interpretation for the entire sentence is that for most of the people who drink (alcohol) it holds that they drink at night. This interpretation is not in conflict with our world knowledge, and it is in fact the optimal (that is, preferred) interpretation against an empty context. Of course, in the presence of an actual context, another interpretation might become optimal. So, the sentence Most people DRINK at night might be used as an answer to the question why there are so many empty beds in the middle of the night, with a concomitant interpretation. Again, this interpretation would deviate from the interpretation dictated by the syntactic structure of the sentence alone. In these cases, in the competition between a syntactically optimal but pragmatically unlikely interpretation and a pragmatically optimal but syntactically suboptimal interpretation, the latter wins. The advantage of an optimization approach to interpretation is clearly that it can deal with actual conflicts among different factors.

برای دانلود رایگان متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

منابع مشابه

The Cancer Stem Cell Hypothesis in Oral Squamous Cell Carcinoma: A New Target for the Treatment

Within a single tumor clone, cells have significantly different abilities to proliferate and form new tumors. This has led to the hypothesis that most cells in a cancer have a limited ability to divide and only a small subset of distinct cells, the cancer stem cells (CSCs), has the capacity to self-renew and form new tumors . It has been proposed that the development of tumors is based exclusiv...

متن کامل

TESTING STATISTICAL HYPOTHESES UNDER FUZZY DATA AND BASED ON A NEW SIGNED DISTANCE

This paper deals with the problem of testing statisticalhypotheses when the available data are fuzzy. In this approach, wefirst obtain a fuzzy test statistic based on fuzzy data, and then,based on a new signed distance between fuzzy numbers, we introducea new decision rule to accept/reject the hypothesis of interest.The proposed approach is investigated for two cases: the casewithout nuisance p...

متن کامل

A New Method for Sperm Detection in Infertility Cure: Hypothesis Testing Based on Fuzzy Entropy Decision

In this paper, a new method is introduced for sperm detection in microscopic images for infertility treatment. In this method, firstly a hypothesis testing function is defined to separate sperms from plasma, non-sperm semen particles and noise. Then, some primary candidates are selected for sperms by watershed-based segmentation algorithm. Finally, candidates are either confirmed or rejected us...

متن کامل

Measuring the compositionality of NV expressions in Basque by means of distributional similarity techniques

We present several experiments aiming at measuring the semantic compositionality of NV expressions in Basque. Our approach is based on the hypothesis that compositionality can be related to distributional similarity. The contexts of each NV expression are compared with the contexts of its corresponding components, by means of different techniques, as similarity measures usually used with the Ve...

متن کامل

A New Method for Root Detection in Minirhizotron Images: Hypothesis Testing Based on Entropy-Based Geometric Level Set Decision

In this paper a new method is introduced for root detection in minirhizotron images for root investigation. In this method firstly a hypothesis testing framework is defined to separate roots from background and noise. Then the correct roots are extracted by using an entropy-based geometric level set decision function. Performance of the proposed method is evaluated on real captured images in tw...

متن کامل

A Constructive Proof On the Compositionality of Linearizability

Linearizability is the strongest correctness property for both shared memory and message passing concurrent systems. One promising nature of linearizability is the compositionality: a history(execution) is linearizable if and only if each object subhistory is linearizable, which is instructive in that we are able to design, implement and test a whole system from the bottom up. In this paper, we...

متن کامل

ذخیره در منابع من


  با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید

عنوان ژورنال:

دوره   شماره 

صفحات  -

تاریخ انتشار 2003